Stefan Brüggemann, Today I Misunderstood, 2002; print on canvas; 58 2/3 x 46 1/16 inches |
J.C. Fregnan / Stefan Brüggemann
“[A]ll bricolages are not equally worthwhile.”— Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology“The pure work of art implies the elocutionary disappearance of the poet, who yields the initiative to words, set in motion by the clash of their inequalities... Everything becomes suspense, a fragmentary disposition with alternations and oppositions, all working towards the total rhythm of the white spaces, which would be the poem silenced.”
— Stéphane Mallarmé, Crise du versCURATOR has long been a pliable signifier. A direct loan from Latin, it derives from the transitive verb curare, which meant both “to cure” in its various senses and, generically, “to be in charge of.” This pliability was distended further when, some centuries after its import into English, the noun curator was back-formed into the pseudo-Latinate verb “to curate.” While the neologism retained curare’s transitivity, the particular set of objects with which it engaged began to broaden: curare implied the administration of people and bodies (human) or, when curing meat, animals; with the linguistic advent of curation, this subject-object relationship opened up to include the administration or arrangement of things. This transition marks a certain horizon of curatorial signification: suddenly a curator-subject was empowered—indeed, expected—to announce elocutionary presence, to say nothing of virtuosity, in and through the meaningful ordering of objects. 1 Insofar as Modern and contemporary art practices have challenged the specific materiality or substantiality of art objects, the concept of curation has had to accommodate immaterial or insubstantial kinds of artistic projects that might nevertheless be organized into a legible, meaningful order. This historical generalization of the objects of curation has had the effect of reducing its concept to a set of relationships between order and meaning and, consequently, authorizes the designation of any practice of ordering as curation. The programming of a concert series, be it for Lincoln Center or the Vans Warped Tour, meets the criteria of curation. Editing a magazine is curation; writing an essay is curation. Roman Jakobson’s theory of the poetic function of language attempts to specify precisely those relationships between order and meaning that would animate and organize this generalized curatorial locution.2 Poetics, in his analysis, is a production of meaning that establishes an equivalence between two processes: selection and combination. He describes the former as a process in which one element is selected from a series of grammatically (but not aesthetically) interchangeable units. The pronoun “he” would be grammatically interchangeable with the proper noun “Jean-Christophe,” for example; the verb “writes” with “prestidigitates.” In a more conventionally art-specific context, the analogous units of selection would be an individual work of art or, alternatively, the work of an individual artist in a group show. The unit thus selected is then combined with others in a horizontal chain. The poetic value of this combination emerges from the correspondence between the two processes: “he writes” versus “Jean-Christophe prestidigitates.” Or this particular piece of art juxtaposed with that particular piece inscribes a meaning that neither piece could produce in isolation. Such a model of poetics would seem to guarantee a place for a signifying curator-subject. (Indeed, curation is considered deficient when the selection and combination of art too openly narrates the curator’s own subjectivity: that is, when curation is clearly motivated by profiteering or nepotism or careerism or personal taste.) Unacknowledged in Jakobson’s account, however, is the radical consequence that according to poetics reduced to the two-dimensional plane of selection and combination, any and all practices of ordering produce meaning. The categorical distinction between production and consumption thus loses its rigor, and with it the specific subjectivity of the curator: if the program director of a concert series produces curatorial meaning, then so, too, does any bored festivalgoer who ambles idly from stage to stage. So, too, does the engineer who designs the algorithm according to which digital tuners selectively identify radio signals; so, too, does the government administrator who regulates radio stations’ applications for assigned carrier frequencies. And so on. What these examples make clear is that the possibility of curatorial meaning bears no necessary connection to the poetic intention of curator-subject. The generalizability of curation is not something to lament. Nor does the omnipresence of the generalized curator-subject herald the obsolescence or impossibility of curatorial practice. Rather, it should stimulate us, curator-subjects and curator-audiences alike, to develop the signifying possibilities of curation even further. Most urgent for this development is the question of where we might locate an irreducibly curatorial meaning that cannot be assimilated to ordering in general. We might well begin by reexamining the foundations of Jakobson’s model of poetics to better articulate it with curation’s specificities.
Stefan Brüggemann, Nothing at all, 2003; print on canvas; 58 2/3 x 46 1/16 inches |
1. The medical ordering of bodies, too, was—and is—a signifying practice. The possibility of signification in such cases, however, inheres bilaterally in the subjectivities of both curator and cured.
2. See “Closing statement: Linguistics and poetics” in Semiotics: An introductory anthology, edited by Robert Innis (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1985).
3. I am grateful to Andrea Paasch for her swift and able translations. Emphasis are mine.
-Rachael
No comments:
Post a Comment